|
The first edition of the 4 volume set William Shakespeare's Sonnet Philosophy [2005] is still available. |
From Duchamp to
|
Contents
|
||
Introduction |
Page |
|
A brief meeting Programme Aesthetics and ethics Wittgenstein, Darwin, and Shakespeare Philosophy versus psychology Focusing on the philosophical The consequences of de Duve's approach A systematic philosophy
|
3 4 4 7 8 11 15 16
|
|
Chapter 1 Marcel Duchamp: Aesthetics |
||
Subject matter Form and content Beyond taste Limitation of formalism for reading Duchamp Content from the past The aesthetic dynamic out of mythic content Octavio Paz Stephane Mallarmé The erotic in Duchamp's work The priority of the sexual over the erotic The sexual and erotic as the 4th and 3rd dimensions The aesthetic The beauty of indifference The mythic logic out of the sexual/erotic dynamic The relation of the readymades to the Large Glass The tube of paint as a readymade Kant and the beautiful Rectifying Kant Summary
|
17 18 22 26 27 29 31 32 35 38 40 45 49 52 53 56 57 59 61
|
|
Chapter 2 Ludwig Wittgenstein: the logical |
||
The wrong paradigm Wittgenstein's method Where the method failed The trajectory of Wittgenstein's thought The atomic model does not provide the correct multiplicity The metaphor of life Summary
|
63 64 65 67 69 70 73
|
|
Chapter 3 Charles Darwin: the biological |
||
Darwin's consistent method Misunderstandings Evolution and the sexual Mental powers and moral sense Darwin the philosopher Priority of the female Body and mind Inherent purpose Summary
|
75 75 77 78 79 80 81 83 85
|
|
Chapter 4 William Shakespeare: the Nature template |
||
Review The Sonnets The uniqueness of the Sonnets The logical dynamic of life The relation of the Large Glass to the Sonnets The basic structure and numbering of the Large Glass The basic structure and numbering of the Sonnets The Large Glass and the Sonnets A logical numbering system The sexual and the erotic in the Large Glass The sexual and the erotic in the Sonnets Sonnets 15 to 19 Eroticism in sonnets 20 to 154 The pattern of 14s The aesthetic and ethical dynamic of the Large Glass The aesthetic and ethical dynamic of the Sonnets Body and mind: the Nature template The role of the Poet The mythic dynamic of the Large Glass The mythic dynamic of the Sonnets Duchamp's limit; Shakespeare's range Summary
|
87 89 90 92 93 94 95 98 99 100 100 103 104 105 107 107 111 113 114 116 118 120
|
|
Chapter 5 Postscript from Shakespeare to Duchamp |
||
Darwin's limit, Shakespeare's range Wittgenstein's limit, Shakespeare's range The limitation of Thierry de Duve's formalism Reinstating the complete paradigm Conclusion: the quaternary dynamic A comparison of thinkers
|
121 122 124 125 126 127
|
|
In the conversation with Thierry de Duve I remember mentioning
Duchamp’s repeated claim that eroticism was the irreducible feature of his
life’s work, and that it was principally from Stephane Mallarmé that
Duchamp had developed this seemingly singular understanding. Duchamp
had said that art should return to the direction Mallarmé traced.
Viewed from the vantage of Duchamp’s achievement, Mallarmé’s poetic
investment of everyday objects, or situations, with a refined eroticism,
combined with a critical awareness of the process of writing, had lifted his
poetry beyond the expectations of mere Symbolism to an accomplishment
of near mythic proportions. In turn, Duchamp’s work lifted Mallarmé’s
profound symbolism to the mythic level by articulating the logical conditions
for eroticism out of the sexual.
Thierry de Duve had difficulty grasping what was being suggested. I was surprised as I was putting forward ideas about the mythic dimension in
Duchamp’s work developed from the mythological critique presented by
Octavio Paz in such books as The Castle of Purity and Appearance Stripped
Bare. My suggestions were also based on Duchamp’s statements regarding
the importance of eroticism for the Large Glass and his other works. He had
said a number of times that eroticism was the only thing he would always
be ‘serious’ about and that it was the ‘platform’ for all his works.
As the conversation progressed it was apparent Thierry de Duve had not considered the pivotal role of eroticism in Duchamp’s art. Because of the
impasse, the conversation turned to his forthcoming book Kant after
Duchamp. He gave some reasons for a delay in publication and then it was
time to return to the conference.
About a year after our meeting in Wellington, in March 1995, I discovered a significant relationship between the work of Duchamp and
the philosophy of Shakespeare’s Sonnets. By chance I had attended a reading
of the complete set of 154 Sonnets, and immediately intuited a philosophic
sensibility corresponding to one I had developed from Mallarmé and
Duchamp (as well as from Wittgenstein and Darwin) over the previous
twenty-five years.
The Sonnets can be shown to be a philosophic presentation of the relationship between the biological processes (nature, female/male and
increase) and the dynamic of ethics and aesthetics (truth and beauty) at the
level of the mythic that encompasses and completes the more specialised
achievements of Duchamp and the above thinkers. The unprecedented
insight into Shakespeare’s philosophy confirmed the soundness of my earlier
intuitions regarding Duchamp. So when Thierry de Duve says, at the end
of his Kant after Duchamp, that a rationale for Duchamp’s achievement still
escapes him, my work suggests that a different approach is required from
the one he has persisted with.
Programme
In this critique I will be arguing that Duchamp’s work expresses the logical
conditions for the aesthetic dynamic in art at the mythic level. Duchamp
was fully cognizant not only of the formal requirements for painting and other
forms of artistic expression, (the formal aspect is, as I see it, the principal
concern of de Duve’s work) but also recognised the determining criteria
for content in art (the principal concern in Octavio Paz’ attempt to understand
the mythical dimension in Duchamp’s work).
Duchamp demonstrated an exceptional proficiency in the formal aspects of artistic practice. To arrive at a comprehensive understanding of his work,
however, more than his mastery of form needs to be considered. His mastery
of the philosophic elements that constitute the mythic content of an artwork
should also be taken into account. This is particularly the case if, as a development
of Paz’ work, it can be suggested that Duchamp identified the
mythic elements in art from which all content can be logically derived.
I will be demonstrating that Duchamp explored the aesthetic dynamic
with a rigour and consistency that enabled him to represent the philosophic
basis of the mythic in art. He expressed this both in the complex imagery
of his two major works, the Large Glass (1912-26) and the tableau Etant
donnes (1946-68), and in the minimal gesture of the readymades.
It is evident from Thierry de Duve’s writings on Duchamp that he has responded principally to the formal influence of the readymades on the avant-garde of the mid-to-late twentieth century. He seems to see the readymades
as if down a narrow tunnel of eight decades of formalist art practice.
While acknowledging Duchamp’s influence on the avant-garde, the
philosophic approach presented here examines the way in which he was able
to make substantial works such as the Large Glass and Etant donnes, with their critical mythic content, as well as works in which such content is reduced
to an ‘infra-thin’ presence, as in the readymades. If the readymades are an
extremely reduced artistic expression based on the same inherent understanding
as Duchamp’s major works then it should be possible to demonstrate
the way in which the readymades have their logical basis in the mythic
dynamic expressed in the Large Glass.
The primarily formal concern of the theoretically sanctioned avantgarde art history of the last few decades (de Duve’s concern) can then be
contrasted to the way in which form and content are inextricably
entwined in the whole of Duchamp’s oeuvre. It should be possible to
demonstrate why artists and theorists, such as Joseph Kosuth and Clement
Greenberg, have ended championing such limited artistic positions when,
in response or in reaction to Duchamp’s achievement, they have ignored
its major premise (the Large Glass) and have responded only to an aspect
of its minor premise (the readymades).
Before considering Duchamp’s achievement I should stress the logical
distinction between the aesthetic and ethical modes of understanding.
The primary meaning of the word aesthetic is ‘a sensation or perception unmediated by thought’ (OED). This meaning, from the Greek, differs from
the eighteenth century, Baumgarten/Kantian, redefinition of aesthetic to
refer to the beautiful, to matters of taste, or to the establishment of aesthetics
as a science.
I will be demonstrating that Duchamp was aware that the primary meaning of aesthetic ensures philosophic clarity, while the eighteenth
century redefinition leads to philosophic confusion. Thierry de Duve does
sense such clarity in Duchamp’s work. However, because of his narrowed
focus on a secondary feature of the readymades he is not able to see how a
philosopher like Emmanuel Kant was confused about aesthetics.
Furthermore, he is not able to appreciate the way in which Kant misrepresented the logical relationship between aesthetics and ethics. Hence,
in Kant after Duchamp, de Duve has difficulty relating the ethical system of
Kant to the aesthetics of Duchamp, a task made more difficult by his use of
Kant’s illogical phrase ‘aesthetic judgment’.
Ethics, in contrast with aesthetics, is the relation of ideas, or the dynamic of thought and expression in language. In keeping with the traditional
distinction between ideas and sensations, ideas derive from sensations whether
the sensations originate in the external world or in the mind. Logically, as
Shakespeare understands it, the aesthetic is any form of sensation and the
ethical is any intentional association of ideas. A more complete explanation of
the dynamic of the aesthetic/ethical relationship is given below.
Duchamp’s insight into the logic of aesthetics and Shakespeare’s understanding of the dynamic of aesthetics and ethics derives from their appreciation of the logic of mythic expression. They understand that the
relationship between female and male in nature is central to mythic expression
because it is the logical basis for the relationship between aesthetics and
ethics. The sexual differentiation of male from female in nature (as in the
Sonnets and the Large Glass) is the logical precondition for the differentiation of ideas from sensations in human expression.
Kant’s use of the phrase ‘aesthetic judgment’, for instance, to characterise transcendental expectations is contradictory. He attempted to characterise,
through a conjunction of two ideas, or the process of ethics, what is logically
an aesthetic event, or a sensation. The phrase ‘aesthetic judgment’ reduces
to the conundrum ‘aesthetic ethics’, just as Wittgenstein’s statement ‘ethics
and aesthetics are one and the same’ reduces to ‘aesthetics and aesthetics are
one and the same’.
Kant’s apologetically driven limitation of the primary meaning of aesthetic (as all sensations) to mean the ‘beautiful’ minus the ‘disgusting’ (or
a preferred class of sensations) was the consequence of believing literally in
mythological expression. Although Kant rejected most mythological
imagery in his critique of youthful beliefs, he maintained a belief in the
mythology of a male God as ‘author’. From the vantage of a consistent
philosophy, the contradiction in asserting that aesthetics is a process of
judgment and that ethics is conditional on the existence of an exemplary
male God, by apologists such as Kant, is readily apparent.
Similarly, to talk of a ‘science of aesthetics’, if the aesthetic is unmediated sensation, as if it was possible to transcend the effects of sensation, is contradictory. Science is logically a function of ethics or the dynamic of language.
Logically the ‘science of aesthetics’ reduces to the ‘ethics of aesthetics’.
Scientific investigation frequently attempts to limit the influence of aesthetics, while artistic expression attempts to limit the role of ethics. But
aesthetic effects and ethical determinations are a natural continuum. Pure
aesthetic states are imaginary just as ethical determinations are defeasible.
Art has at least a little ethics and frequently a large dose of ethics as part of
its expression. Similarly science cannot avoid the effect of aesthetics, as is
the case in scientific investigations where sensations critically affect the possibility
of objective readings.
Duchamp’s unvarying procedure for achieving an aesthetic expression
in art can be summarised as an attempt to limit the influence of ethics or
the logic of language. His catch cry was ‘reduce, reduce, reduce’. The mere
existence, however, of his many explanatory notes in the Box of 1914, the
Green Box, and the White Box tacitly acknowledges the logical impossibility
of achieving a complete removal of ethics from art.
Wittgenstein, Darwin, and Shakespeare
To explore the logic of the ethical I will be introducing aspects of the thought of Ludwig Wittgenstein. If Duchamp’s work expresses the basic philosophic conditions for art, Wittgenstein’s work provides an understanding of the
philosophic conditions for language. This is not to say that Wittgenstein’s
understanding of the nature of aesthetics and ethics is logically sound.
He, as with most philosophers, misconstrues the relationship. But, despite
Wittgenstein’s misunderstanding of the aesthetic/ethical dynamic, his analysis
of the logic of language can be used to reveal the nature of the ethical.
The critique will consider Wittgenstein’s use of ‘true’and ‘false’ in relation to propositions, his attempt to determine the logical multiplicity between
language and the world, his conditions for certainty of knowledge, and his
notion of language games where he uses biological metaphors such as ‘family
resemblances’ and the concept ‘forms of life’. Even if Wittgenstein’s understanding
of the relationship of biology and the mind was inconsistent, he
went further than most in his attempt to resolve the illogical consequences of
the traditional representation of the relationship of language and the world.
To help clarify the logical relation between aesthetics and ethics, I will refer to Charles Darwin’s argument from The Descent of Man and Selection in
Relation to Sex for the relation of biological or sexual processes to ‘mental
powers’ and the ‘moral sense’. Darwin understood that the evolutionary
biology of the human species was consistent with the development of human
understanding. In Part I, ‘The Descent or Origin of Man’, and Parts II and
III, ‘Selection through Secondary Sexual Characteristics’ he deals with the
sexual and the erotic respectively. The logic of the sexual dynamic establishes
the possibility of the erotic as the underlying condition for art. I will
be showing that Duchamp’s notion of 4th dimension is the sexual dynamic,
or what he called the ‘given’.
It is the philosophy of William Shakespeare, though, that provides a comprehensive overview of Duchamp’s accomplishment. In the Sonnets,
Shakespeare prefigured by 300 years the mythic critique of art apparent in
the Large Glass. The Sonnets present the nature-based logic of the relation
between the sexual and the erotic necessary for mythic expression. Shakespeare
incorporates into the structure of the Sonnets the logical relationship
of the ethical to the aesthetic (‘truth and beauty’) and he bases their logical
relationship on the sexual dynamic presented in the increase sonnets. For
Shakespeare, the aesthetic is any form of sensation (in the Sonnets ‘beauty’
is archetypically ‘seeing’) and the ethical is any intentional association of ideas
(‘truth’ is identified with ‘saying’ in the Sonnets).
I will show how the achievements of Duchamp, Wittgenstein, and Darwin, can be combined to arrive at the philosophic clarity of Shakespeare’s Sonnets.
Philosophy versus psychology
Before considering the consequences of Thierry de Duve’s focus on only a few of Duchamp’s readymades, I want to stress the importance of his decision to consider Duchamp philosophically. Other commentators on Duchamp,
such as Arturo Schwarz and John Golding, have relied heavily on psychological
analyses and even a critic as perceptive about the ‘mythical’ content
in Duchamp’s work as Octavio Paz does not approach Duchamp with the
required philosophic acuity.
I acknowledge de Duve’s decision, in Pictorial Nominalism, to move from a psychological approach to a philosophical one because of the inappropriateness of attempting to understand Duchamp’s work from a psychological
basis. His decision reminds me of Leo Bersani’s caution in The Death of
Mallarmé where he put aside his psychological hat the better to deal with
the philosophic demands of Mallarmé’s poetry. And de Duve’s decision to
relate Kant to Duchamp in Kant after Duchamp at least recognises that
Duchamp’s philosophic accomplishment supersedes the aesthetic philosophy
of the ‘greatest philosopher of the modern period
De Duve’s more philosophical approach to Duchamp is evident in the criticism he directs at the excessive psychotherapy and alchemical speculation
in Schwarz’ account of Duchamp’s work.
The alchemical and cabalistic readings of Duchamp are mystifying, since, quite obviously, their interpretive systems derive from an archaic mode of knowledge, not only one that existed prior to the interpreted system but also one that uses the interpreted system as if it were the blots in an inkblot test. The same is true for certain pseudoclinical psychoanalytic readings of Duchamp such as Schwarz’s or Held’s. Their problem is not just that they conduct their analyses in the absence of the subject, since Freud himself did that. Above all, what is wrong is that this sort of psychoanalysis is historically anterior – and epistemologically inferior – to the analyzed artwork. Duchamp’s acute practice finds itself decoded there through symbolist grids infinitely looser than itself and therefore without any relevance. (1)
De Duve’s criticism of the arcane aspects of Schwarz’, Golding’s, and similar readings, is warranted in that such readings do not and cannot do
justice to Duchamp’s philosophic accomplishment.
However, the passage also reveals the inadequacy of de Duve’s understanding of the role of philosophy. It does not follow that all knowledge ‘that
existed prior to the interpreted system’ is invalid. Besides being logically
unsound, his anti-historicist rationale is inconsistent with Duchamp’s
frequent assertion that he wanted to return art to the ‘ideas’ of the Renaissance
and other periods before the modern era. In this regard, de Duve’s
writing can be subjected to the same criticism he makes of Schwarz and
others. If Schwarz mismatched inadequate and inappropriate systems of
symbolism to the work of Duchamp, then de Duve, by focusing principally
on a few readymades and the formalist art history of Modernism that
Duchamp rejected, develops an interpretation of Duchamp’s work that is
philosophically inferior to the work.
De Duve’s assertions, even though they are made within living memory of Duchamp, can be shown to be less sound than logical claims based on a
sound philosophy from a previous era. I will show that Shakespeare in the
sixteenth century and Darwin in the nineteenth century developed a sound
philosophy consistent with the philosophic achievement of Duchamp in the
twentieth century. I will be drawing on the logical connections between
Duchamp’s work and the achievements of Shakespeare and Darwin because
they operated with the same degree of philosophic acuity.
By contrast, Kant, albeit as an apologist for the Christian God reduced to a practical necessity, produced a philosophy constrained by the psychology
of his beliefs and so fails to meet the logical criteria. Only in the logically
acute context of a Shakespearean mind, free of cant, can de Duve’s prioritisation
of issues as peripheral as ‘pictorial nominalism’ and ‘colour’ find their
correct logical relation. Their role within Duchamp’s overall achievement
requires an appropriate level of philosophic insight.
So despite a determination to approach Duchamp philosophically, de Duve’s analysis remains affected by psychological traits. In Pictorial Nominalism, for instance, he decides to persist with the comparison, albeit a ‘parallel
one’, of Freud’s ‘Dream of Irma’ with aspects of Duchamp’s work. While
the strategy is not as speculative as that of Schwarz, it still leads to illogical
or psychological conclusions. For instance, de Duve modifies Schwarz’
suggestion Duchamp had an incestuous relationship with his sister Suzanne
into the disingenuous idea he was consciously playing off whatever feelings
he experienced towards ‘Suzanne’ onto the objectivity of an artistic
relationship with ‘Cezanne’. Even though it seems de Duve is focusing
on matters aesthetic more philosophically, the aesthetic possibility is still
conditioned by the suggestion Duchamp was influenced by unsublimated
personal experiences.
De Duve’s attempt to characterise Duchamp’s work as meta-psychological presumes he had a psychological problem to overcome and that the
problem drove his artistic ambitions. The fallacy is that while the circumstances
of life do contribute to insights or realisations, in Duchamp’s case
his artistic accomplishment is so logically sound it transcends the
psychology that may have been part of its genesis. It is pointless then to
attempt to understand his philosophic clarity through psychological speculation.
Such an approach cannot generate the required philosophic insight.
Duchamp, by all accounts, was psychologically at ease before and after the period of his artistic breakthrough. Because clinical psychology presumes a problem that requires a cure, and because Freud and Jung were not philosophers
but sought to cure diseases of the mind through psychoanalysis or
psychotherapy, any attempt to explain Duchamp’s achievement through
psychology must fail. When someone is said to be psychological, a disorder
of the mind is implied, but if such issues have been mastered, a person is
capable of being philosophical. Whereas psychology deals with conditions
of the mind, philosophy deals with the logical relation that persists between
the mind and the world.
I will be showing that Duchamp’s artistic accomplishment is deeply philosophic. And because Shakespeare accounts for the logical relationship
between the biological and the conditions for mythic understanding and
expression, his work needs to be understood in the most rigorous philosophic
terms.
Focusing on the philosophical
In Thierry de Duve’s attempt to avoid the biographical cum psychological analyses that nauseously plague the works of Duchamp (Shakespeare’s Sonnets have been subjected to a similar litany of inadequate readings) he resorts to
both contemporary art history and a selection of items of philosophical
interest from Duchamp’s Notes.
To address the historical significance of the readymades de Duve relates Duchamp’s work to that of Paul Cezanne, Cubism, the Succession, and the process of avant-garde change. This at least has the virtue of focusing the debate more on the art and less on the person. To address issues that have
no obvious psychological connotations he focuses on the more philosophical
elements in Duchamp’s Notes. He selects a few of Duchamp’s tersest
comments in an attempt to make sense of his work.
The philosophically imbued comment, ‘a sort of pictorial nominalism’, the ‘algebraic comparison a/b’, Duchamp’s focus on the syntax rather than
on the semantics of ‘colour’, and his determination to make something that
both ‘was and was not a work of art’, all provide at least a glimpse into his
appreciation of the logic of aesthetics. Nominalism, particularly, seems
readymade for the task. It has a philosophical pedigree and Duchamp
mentions it both in his Notes and in his interviews.
It seems, however, that Duchamp was not identifying himself solely or even principally as a nominalist, nor was he characterising every aspect of
his procedures as nominalistic. He talks of ‘a sort of pictorial nominalism’.
At most, it seems, in his descriptive and qualified use of the term, he wanted
to convey something of the difference between art as a retinal activity, where
the artist seeks to create a Platonic or ideal ‘world’, and art as a conceptual
or nominal process that acknowledges the futility of such an expectation.
Duchamp saw his work offering ‘a sort of pictorial nominalism’ to challenge
the presumptuousness of artists’ claims to be expressing or divining a
Platonically ‘real’ category called ‘art’. In their logical rigour the philosophic
critique in his works is anti-Platonist.
In Pictorial Nominalism, by contrast, de Duve characterises Duchamp’s whole enterprise under the rubric of the limited philosophical position of nominalism. He seems determined to demonstrate a wholly nominalistic
rationale for the readymades. He presents the readymades as Duchamp’s final farewell to painting because he is determined to reduce painterly activity,
in terms of readymade tubes of paint, canvas, etc., to the very circumscribed
‘nominal’ statement ‘this is art’. True, in this formal or technical sense of
nominalism, ‘art’ could not then be considered a Platonist state with an
existence apart from the reality of the readymade paint and canvas. But such
a limited formalist rationale has illogical consequences for de Duve’s interpretation
of the significance of the other works in Duchamp’s oeuvre.
De Duve’s pursuit of this rationale led, if not directly, to the extraordinary assertion in Pictorial Nominalism, that The Passage from the Virgin to the Bride is the pivotal work in Duchamp’s oeuvre. This was because it needed to be, for his purposes, the work at the transition point between the history
of painting, the ‘tube of paint’ tradition as practised by those like Cezanne,
and an avant-garde ‘naming’ of the readymades as ‘art’.
The idea that the readymades were similar to named ‘tubes of paint’which nominalistically liberated the notion of art from its allegiance to the factured canvas of ‘retinal’ art to herald unmitigated conceptual intent is no doubt
one of the possible implications of Duchamp’s use of the phrase ‘a sort of
pictorial nominalism’. Duchamp’s conditional reference to the idea of
nominalism, though, would seem to suggest that it was not the philosophic
position from out of which he engineered the mythic content of the Large
Glass and the rest of his oeuvre.
Despite the majority of commentators agreeing with Duchamp’s statements, expressed in his Notes and interviews, that the Large Glass was the central and most important work of his whole oeuvre, de Duve requires
the Passage from the Virgin to the Bride to be the pivotal work to support his
formalist understanding of the readymades. Yet the evidence in Duchamp’s
notes suggests the Passage was a ‘study’ for the Large Glass, and the Large Glass was the centre-piece in his miniaturised museum Box in a Valise around
which he intentionally grouped the readymades and the Passage from the Virgin
to the Bride and all his other works.
In Pictorial Nominalism de Duve’s focus on Duchamp’s qualified reference to pictorial nominalism, and his persistence with a psychological analysis of Duchamp’s intentions (though less presumptuous than Schwarz’), leads to a conclusion at odds with the pre-eminence of the Large Glass in Duchamp’s oeuvre. De Duve’s reading needs to be weighed against the aspects of
Duchamp’s work that cannot be explained by a nominalist thesis and against
those aspects of his work that he stated a number of times were central to
its interpretation.
The formalist rationale in de Duve’s critique of Duchamp is similar to that made by Wassily Kandinsky about his own early work in Concerning the
Spiritual in Art. Ignoring the earthy sensuality of the early works he proposed
instead a pseudo-spiritual rationale for artistic expression. Kandinsky’s
isolation of an aspect of his earlier work from its matrix of artistic creativity
led directly to the arid abstraction of his later work. Similarly, de Duve isolates
an aspect of Duchamp’s work with a rationale that lacks the capacity to
account for the mythic depth and persistent complexity of his whole oeuvre.
As the Large Glass came after the Passage from the Virgin to the Bride, and so had to be retrospectively accounted for in the light of de Duve’s claim for nominalist function of the readymades, it became for him merely an ironic critique of previous art practice.
Duchamp made the Large Glass in the manner of a conscientious but stupid artisan ... But he also thought of the Large Glass as the ironic staging of this craft and its stupidity. (2)For the sake of de Duve’s theory, the Large Glass had to be reduced to something of an anachronism. There could be no possibility that it was both an ironic critique of previous art practice and an encompassing expression of the mythic dynamic basic to all art. For the sake of his analysis it was not possible for the Large Glass to demonstrate both a mastery of the form and articulate the logical conditions for mythic content in art.
It (the Large Glass) works around the bar and accomplishes the mourning of painting, not so much as possible/impossible, but as useless. (3)
The consequences of de Duve’s approach
De Duve’s thesis applies to one, two or maybe three of Duchamp’s twenty or so readymades. Not only does he leave all the other readymades of various types and other occasional works out of his analysis but he also leaves out the Large Glass, Etant donnes, and all the pre-1912 work that Duchamp assiduously included in the Box in a Valise, and gathered together for the
permanent collection in the Philadelphia Museum of Art.
Not only that, de Duve also persists in calling the Fountain the ‘Urinal’ and talks of it as if its title, its reorientation in space (around the physiological hinge point of the groin), the signature ‘R Mutt’, and the article in
The Blind Man, were of no consequence in terms of authorial invention.
It seems rather obvious that de Duve’s artistic alter ego (who he manipulates to say ‘This is Art’) in no way replicates Duchamp’s achievement
of giving a mythic level of content to the found objects he converts to
readymades. De Duve derives some of his authority to use the incredibly
reductive statement ‘This is Art’ from Duchamp’s recognition that the public
determined at any one time what was to be called art and what was not. I
will demonstrate that it does not follow that this was Duchamp’s modus
operandi and hence the saying of the phrase ‘This is Art’ cannot be used as a
nominating process in imitation of Duchamp.
The critique demonstrates the consequences of de Duve’s decision to severely limit the reading of Duchamp’s oeuvre to a few works. It will show
that de Duve used the philosophical concerns of Kant more as chapter
headings for a simplistic reading of Duchamp rather than as a means to
produce a substantial critique of Kant in the light of Duchamp’s aesthetic
brilliance. Because Duchamp’s understanding of aesthetics is logically
consistent, even his preference for aesthetics over ethics correctly locates
aesthetics in relation to ethics, and the sexual in relation to the erotic,
allowing a full critique of Kant’s inconsistencies.
A systematic philosophy
The critique shows that Duchamp’s appreciation of the philosophic status of aesthetics is central to his accomplishment. This resolves into two crucial realisations.
In the first, Duchamp the aesthete understood implicitly, if not explicitly, that for an artwork to be reduced to the aesthetic dimension of its mythic
dynamic it must attempt to divest itself of the ethical. Throughout his life
Duchamp consistently avoided propositional language, particularly the verbal
critical process. In everything he made he worked to eliminate ‘difference’.
He expressed a preference for individuals and a disdain for groups. He
appreciated that ‘indifference’ is the hallmark of the aesthetic even if he did
not explore the logical consequence that ‘difference’ is the hallmark of the
ethical.
In the second, Duchamp, from the evidence of his Notes, understood that there is a logical distinction between the sexual and the erotic. The dynamic is expressed in the Large Glass, Etant donnes, and is evident in every readymade and incidental work he made. The non-consummation of the
relationship between the Bride and the Bachelors acknowledges the sexual
as a biological process outside the domain of art. The corollary is that erotics,
as the function of desire in the mind, cannot, of itself, replace the sexual or
the biological potential to produce a child.
The second condition is the more basic and was recognised as such by Duchamp when he stated that the erotic was the only thing about which
he would always be serious. The critique shows that the erotic logically
conditions both ethics and aesthetics (or ideas and sensations). For this reason
Duchamp had to constrain the ethical artificially to allow the logic of the
aesthetic to become critically apparent. Hence he used irony and humour
to counter the inevitable reassertion of the ethical in most things he wrote.
The consequence of Duchamp’s concentrated focus on the aesthetic will
emerge later.
With these thoughts in mind I will examine in some detail the statements Marcel Duchamp made about his own works. I will then briefly
consider Stephane Mallarmé, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and Charles Darwin to
reveal an attitude toward life that unites this otherwise unlikely foursome as
seminal exponents of natural logic. Then I will show how their contributions
can be combined to form the Nature template, of which William
Shakespeare provides the most consistent and comprehensive expression.
Notes are numbered continuously throughout the webpages on Darwin, Wittgenstein, Mallarmé, Duchamp to Shakespeare
1 Thierry de Duve, Pictorial Nominalism: On Marcel Duchamp's Passage from Painting to the Readymade, University of Minnesota Press, 1991, p. 8. Back
2 Ibid., p. 175. Back
3 Ibid., p. 176. Back